Archive
The generalized fiducial distribution: A kinder, more objective posterior?
MR3561954
Generalized fiducial inference: a review and new results. (English summary)
J. Amer. Statist. Assoc. 111 (2016), no. 515, 1346–1361.
62A01 (62F99 62G05 62J05)
Other approaches to fiducial inference bring subjectivity more to the forefront. For example, G. N. Wilkinson had highlighted the incoherence of fiducial distributions formulated in a more Fisherian flavor [J. Roy. Statist. Soc. Ser. B 39 (1977), no. 2, 119–171; MR0652326]. More recently, R. J. Bowater [AStA Adv. Stat. Anal. 101 (2017), no. 2, 177–197] endorsed an explicitly subjective interpretation of fiducial probability. For the place of generalized fiducial inference in the context of other fiducial approaches, see [D. L. Sonderegger and J. Hannig, in Contemporary developments in statistical theory, 155–189, Springer Proc. Math. Stat., 68, Springer, Cham, 2014; MR3149921] and the papers it {MR3149921} cites.
- A weak-limit definition of a generalized fiducial distribution.
- Sufficient conditions for a generalized fiducial distribution to have asymptotic frequentist coverage.
- Novel formulas for computing a generalized fiducial distribution and a fiducial probability of a model.
The fiducial probability of a model is applicable to both model selection and model averaging. A seemingly different fiducial method of averaging statistical models was independently proposed by D. R. Bickel [“A note on fiducial model averaging as an alternative to checking Bayesian and frequentist models”, preprint, Fac. Sci. Math. Stat., Univ. Ottawa, 2015].
Reviewed by David R. Bickel
Against ideological philosophies of probability
Burdzy, Krzysztof
Resonance—from probability to epistemology and back. Imperial College Press, London, 2016. xx+408 pp. ISBN: 978-1-78326-920-4
60A05 (00A30 03A10 62A01)
Burdzy defines probability in terms of six “laws of probability”, intended as an accurate description of how probability is used in science (pp. 8–9, 217). Unlike the axiomatic systems from Kolmogorov onward that are distinct from their potential applications [see A. Rényi, Rev. Inst. Internat. Statist 33 (1965), 1–14; MR0181483], the laws require that mathematical probability by definition agree with features of objective events. Potentially subject to scientific or philosophical refutation (pp. 258–259), the laws are analogous to Maxwell’s equations (p. 222). The testable claim is that they accurately describe science’s use of epistemic probabilities as well as physical probabilities (pp. 259–261).
Laws 3, 4, and 6 are especially physical. Burdzy argues that probability theory could not be applied if symmetries such as physical independence (Law 3) could not be recognized and tentatively accepted by resonance (Section 11.4). Such symmetries do not include the law of the iterated logarithm or many other properties of Martin-Löf sequences, which he finds “totally useless from the practical point of view” (Section 4.14). Law 4, the requirement that assigning equal probabilities should be based on known physical symmetries rather than on ignorance (Section 11.25), echoes R. Chuaqui Kettlun’s Truth, possibility and probability [North-Holland Math. Stud., 166, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1991 (Sections III.2 and XX.3); MR1159708]. Law 6 needs some qualification or further explanation since it does not apply directly to continuous random variables: “An event has probability 0 if and only if it cannot occur. An event has probability 1 if and only if it must occur” (p. 217).
There is some dissonance in applications to statistics. On the frequentist side, a confidence interval with a high level of confidence should be used to predict that the parameter value lies within the observed confidence interval (Section 11.11, as explained by pp. 292, 294). Even though that generalizes predicting that the parameter values corresponding to rejected null hypotheses are not equal to the true parameter value, Burdzy expresses doubt about how to formalize hypothesis testing in terms of prediction (Section 13.4). His predictive-testing idea may be seen as an application of Cournot’s principle (pp. 22, 278; see [M. R. Fréchet, Les mathématiques et le concret, Presses Univ. France, Paris, 1955 (pp. 201–202, 209–213, 216–217, 221); MR0075110]). On the Bayesian side, Burdzy concedes that priors based on resonance often work well and yet judges them too susceptible to prejudice for scientific use (Section 14.4.3). By ridiculing subjective Bayesian theory as if it legitimized assigning probabilities at will (Section 7.1), Burdzy calls attention to its failure to specify all criteria for rational probability assignment.
Burdzy adds color to the text with random references to religion from the perspective of an atheistic probabilist who left Catholicism (p. 178). Here are some representative examples. First, in contrast to attempts to demonstrate that an objective probability of God’s existence is low [R. Dawkins, The God delusion, Bantam Press, 2006] or high [R. Swinburne, The resurrection of God incarnate, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 2003], he denies the feasibility of computing such a probability (Section 16.7). Second, Burdzy is convinced that religions, like communism, philosophical theories of probability, and other secular ideologies, have inconsistencies to the point of hypocrisy, insisting that his “resonance’ theory” (p. 13) is not an ideology (Chapter 15), much as D. V. Lindley denied that his Bayesianism is a religion [Understanding uncertainty, revised edition, Wiley Ser. Probab. Stat., Wiley, Hoboken, NJ, 2014 (pp. 380–381); MR3236718]. Lastly, Burdzy attributes the infinite consequences of underlying Pascal’s Wager to efforts to deceive and manipulate (Section 16.2.2). However, documenting the historical origins of teachings of eternal bliss and eternal retribution on the basis of primitive Christian and pre-Christian sources lies far beyond the scope of the book.
Under the resonance banner, this probabilist rushes in with a unique barrage of controversial and well-articulated philosophical claims with implications for science and beyond. Those resisting will find themselves challenged to counter with alternative solutions to the problems raised.
Reviewed by David R. Bickel
Entropies of a posterior of the success probability
Kelbert, M.; Mozgunov, P.
Asymptotic behaviour of the weighted Renyi, Tsallis and Fisher entropies in a Bayesian problem. (English summary)
Eurasian Math. J. 6 (2015), no. 2, 6–17.
94A17 (62B10 62C10)
This paper considers a weighted version of the differential entropy of the posterior distribution of the probability of success conditional on the observed value of a binomial random variable. The uniform (0,1)prior distribution of the success probability is used to derive large-sample results.
The weighting function allows emphasizing some values of the parameter more than other values. For example, since the success probability value of 1/2 has special importance in many applications, that parameter value may be assigned a higher weight than the others. This differs from the more common Bayesian approach of assigning more prior probability to certain parameter values.
The author proves asymptotic properties not only of the weighted differential entropy but also of weighted differential versions of the Renyi, Tsallis, and Fisher definitions of entropy or information. The results are concrete in that they are specifically derived for the posterior distribution of the success probability given the uniform prior.
Reviewed by David R. Bickel
Entropy sightings
Entropy and its many avatars. (English summary)
J. Math. Soc. Japan 67 (2015), no. 4, 1845–1857.
94A17 (37A35 60-02 60K35 82B05)
The author, a chief architect of the theory of large deviations, chronicles several manifestations of entropy. It made appearances in the realms indicated by these section headings:
- Entropy and information theory
- Entropy and dynamical systems
- Relative entropy and large deviations
- Entropy and duality
- Log Sobolev inequality
- Gibbs states
- Interacting particle systems
The topics are connected whenever a concept introduced in one section is treated in more depth in a later section. In this way, relative entropy is seen to play a key role in large deviations, Gibbs states, and systems of interacting particles.
Less explicit connections are left to the reader’s enjoyment and education. For example, the relation between Boltzmann entropy and Shannon entropy in the information theory section is a special case both of Sanov’s theorem, presented in the section on large deviations, and of the relation of free energy and relative entropy, in the section on Gibbs states.
The paper ends with a tribute to Professor Kiyosi Itô.
Reviewed by David R. Bickel
References
- J. Axzel and Z. Daroczy, On Measures of Information and Their Characterizations, Academic Press, New York, 1975. MR0689178
- L. Boltzmann, Über die Mechanische Bedeutung des Zweiten Hauptsatzes der Wärmetheorie, Wiener Berichte, 53 (1866), 195–220.
- R. Clausius, Théorie mécanique de la chaleur, lère partie, Paris: Lacroix, 1868.
- H. Cramer, On a new limit theorem in the theory of probability, Colloquium on the Theory of Probability, Hermann, Paris, 1937.
- J. D. Deuschel and D. W. Stroock, Large deviations, Pure and Appl. Math., 137, Academic Press, Inc., Boston, MA, 1989, xiv+307 pp. MR0997938
- M. D. Donsker and S. R. S. Varadhan, Asymptotic evaluation of certain Markov process expectations for large time, IV, Comm. Pure Appl. Math., 36 (1983), 183–212. MR0690656
- A. Feinstein, A new basic theorem of information theory, IRE Trans. Information Theory PGIT-4 (1954), 2–22. MR0088413
- L. Gross, Logarithmic Sobolev inequalities, Amer. J. Math., 97 (1975), 1061–1083. MR0420249
- M. Z. Guo, G. C. Papanicolaou and S. R. S. Varadhan, Nonlinear diffusion limit for a system with nearest neighbor interactions, Comm. Math. Phys., 118 (1988), 31–59. MR0954674
- A. I. Khinchin, On the fundamental theorems of information theory, Translated by Morris D. Friedman, 572 California St., Newtonville MA 02460, 1956, 84 pp. MR0082924
- A. N. Kolmogorov, A new metric invariant of transitive dynamical systems and automorphisms of Lebesgue spaces, (Russian) Topology, ordinary differential equations, dynamical systems, Trudy Mat. Inst., Steklov., 169 (1985), 94–98, 254. MR0836570
- O. Lanford, Entropy and equilibrium states in classical statistical mechanics, Statistical Mechanics and Mathematical Problems, Lecture notes in Physics, 20, Springer-Verlag, Berlin and New York, 1971, 1–113.
- D. S. Ornstein, Ergodic theory, randomness, and dynamical systems, James K. Whittemore Lectures in Mathematics given at Yale University, Yale Mathematical Monographs, No. 5. Yale University Press, New Haven, Conn.-London, 1974, vii+141 pp. MR0447525
- I. N. Sanov, On the probability of large deviations of random magnitudes, (Russian) Mat. Sb. (N. S.), 42 (84) (1957), 11–44. MR0088087
- C. E. Shannon, A mathematical theory of communication, Bell System Tech. J., 27 (1948), 379–423, 623–656. MR0026286
- Y. G. Sinai, On a weak isomorphism of transformations with invariant measure, (Russian) Mat. Sb. (N.S.), 63 (105) (1964), 23–42. MR0161961
- H. T. Yau, Relative entropy and hydrodynamics of Ginzburg-Landau models, Lett. Math. Phys., 22 (1991), 63–80. MR1121850
Frequentist inference principles
On some principles of statistical inference.
Int. Stat. Rev. 83 (2015), no. 2, 293–308.
62A01 (62F05 62F15 62F25)
While agreeing with other frequentists on the necessity of guaranteeing good performance over repeated sampling, Reid and Cox also value neglected rules of inference such as the conditionality principle. Against the steady advance of nonparametric methods, Reid and Cox point to the interpretive power of parametric models.Frequentist decision theory is only mentioned. Glimpses of the authors’ perspectives on that appear in [D. R. Cox, Principles of statistical inference, Cambridge Univ. Press, Cambridge, 2006 (8.2); MR2278763 (2007g:62007)] and [N. M. Reid, Statist. Sci. 9 (1994), no. 3, 439–455; MR1325436 (95m:01020)].On the Bayes front, Reid and Cox highlight the success frequentist methods have enjoyed in scientific applications as a decisive victory over those Bayesian methods that are most consistent with their subjectivist foundations. Indeed, no one can deny what C. Howson and P. Urbach call the “social success” of frequentist methods [Scientific reasoning: the Bayesian approach, third edition, Open Court, Chicago, IL, 2005 (p. 9)]. Reid and Cox do not attribute their widespread use in scientific practice to political factors.
Rather, for scientific inference as opposed to individual decision making, they find frequentist methods more suitable in principle than fully Bayesian methods. For while the need for an agent to reach a decision recognizes no line between models of the phenomena under study and models of an agent’s thought, science requires clear reporting on the basis of the former without introducing biases from the latter. Although subjective considerations admittedly come into play in interpreting reports of statistical analyses, a dependence of the reports themselves on such considerations conflicts with scientific methodology. In short, the Bayesian theories supporting personal inference are irrelevant as far as science is concerned even if they are useful in personal decision making. This viewpoint stops short of that of Philip Stark, who went as far as to call the practicality of that private application of Bayesian inference into question [SIAM/ASA J. Uncertain. Quantif. 3 (2015), no. 1, 586–598; MR3372107].
On reference priors designed to minimize subjective input, Reid and Cox point out that those that perform well with low-dimensional parameters can fail in high dimensions. Eliminating the prior entirely leads to the pure likelihood approach, which, based on the strong likelihood principle, limits the scope even further, to problems with a scalar parameter of interest and no nuisance parameters [A. W. F. Edwards, Likelihood. An account of the statistical concept of likelihood and its application to scientific inference, Cambridge Univ. Press, London, 1972; MR0348869 (50 #1363)]. More recent developments of that approach were explained by R. M. Royall [Statistical evidence, Monogr. Statist. Appl. Probab., 71, Chapman & Hall, London, 1997; MR1629481 (99f:62012)] and C. A. Rohde [Introductory statistical inference with the likelihood function, Springer, Cham, 2014 (Chapter 18); MR3243684].
Reid and Cox see some utility in Bayesian methods that have good performance by frequentist standards, noting that such performance can require the prior to depend on which parameter happens to be of interest and, through model checking, on the data. Such dependence raises the question, “Is this, then, Bayesian? The prior distribution will then not represent prior knowledge of the parameter in [that] case, but an understanding of the model” [T. Schweder and N. L. Hjort, Scand. J. Statist. 29 (2002), no. 2, 309–332; MR1909788 (2003d:62085)].
Reviewed by David R. Bickel
This review first appeared at “On some principles of statistical inference” (Mathematical Reviews) and is used with permission from the American Mathematical Society.
Meaningful constraints and meaningless priors
Constraints versus priors.
SIAM/ASA J. Uncertain. Quantif. 3 (2015), no. 1, 586–598.
62A01 (62C10 62C20 62G15)
In this lucid expository paper, Stark advances several arguments for using frequentist methods instead of Bayesian methods in statistical inference and decision problems. The main examples involve restricted-parameter problems, those of inferring the value of a parameter of interest that is constrained to lie in an unusually restrictive set. When the parameter is restricted, frequentist methods can lead to solutions markedly different from those of Bayesian methods. For even when the prior distribution is a default intended to be weakly informative, it actually carries substantial information.
Stark calls routine Bayesian practice into question since priors are not selected according to the analyst’s beliefs but rather for reasons that have no apparent support from the Dutch book argument, the featured rationale for Bayesianism as a rational norm (pp. 589–590; [see D. V. Lindley, Understanding uncertainty, revised edition, Wiley Ser. Probab. Stat., Wiley, Hoboken, NJ, 2014; MR3236718]). Uses of the prior beyond the scope of the paper include those encoding (1) empirical Bayes estimates of parameter variability [e.g., B. Efron, Large-scale inference, Inst. Math. Stat. Monogr., 1, Cambridge Univ. Press, Cambridge, 2010; MR2724758 (2012a:62006)], (2) the beliefs of subject-matter experts [e.g., A. O’Hagan et al., Uncertain judgements: eliciting experts’ probabilities, Wiley, West Sussex, 2006, doi:10.1002/0470033312], or (3) the beliefs of archetypical agents of wide scientific interest [e.g., D. J. Spiegelhalter, K. R. Abrams and J. P. Myles, Bayesian approaches to clinical trials and health-care evaluation, Wiley, West Sussex, 2004 (Section 5.5), doi:10.1002/0470092602].
Stark finds Bayesianism to lack not only normative force but also descriptive power. He stresses that he does not know anyone who updates personal beliefs according to Bayes’s theorem in everyday life (pp. 588, 590).
In the conclusions section, Stark asks, “Which is the more interesting question: what would happen if Nature generated a new value of the parameter and the data happened to remain the same, or what would happen for the same value of the parameter if the measurement were repeated?” For the Bayesian who sees parameter distributions more in terms of beliefs than random events, the missing question is, “What should one believe about the value of a parameter given what happened and the information encoded in the prior and other model specifications?” That question would interest Stark only to the extent that the prior encodes meaningful information (p. 589).
Reviewed by David R. Bickel
This review first appeared at “Constraints versus priors” (Mathematical Reviews) and is used with permission from the American Mathematical Society.
Understanding Uncertainty (by Lindley)—a review
Lindley, Dennis V.
Understanding uncertainty.
Revised edition. Wiley Series in Probability and Statistics. John Wiley & Sons, Inc., Hoboken, NJ, 2014. xvi+393 pp. ISBN: 978-1-118-65012-7
62A99 (62C05 62C10)
In Understanding uncertainty, Dennis Lindley ably defends subjective Bayesianism, the thesis that decisions in the presence of uncertainty can only be guaranteed to cohere if made according to probabilities as degrees of someone’s beliefs. True to form, he excludes all other mathematical theories of modeling uncertainty, including subjective theories of imprecise probability that share the goal of coherent decision making [see M. C. M. Troffaes and G. de Cooman, Lower previsions, Wiley Ser. Probab. Stat., Wiley, Chichester, 2014; MR3222242].
In order to engage everyone interested in making better decisions in the presence of uncertainty, Lindley writes without the citations and cluttered notation of a research paper. His straightforward, disarming style advances the thesis that subjective probability saves uncertainty from getting lost in the fog of reasoning in natural-language arguments. A particularly convincing argument is that the reader who makes decisions in conflict with the strict Bayesian viewpoint will be vulnerable to a Dutch book comprising undesirable consequences regardless of the true state of the world (5.7). The axioms needed for the underlying theorem are confidently presented as self-evident.
Like many strict Bayesians, Lindley makes no appeal to epistemological or psychological literature supporting the alignment of belief and probability. In fact, he dismisses studies indicating that actual human beliefs can deviate markedly from the requirements of strict Bayesianism, likening them to studies indicating that people make errors in arithmetic (2.5; 9.12).
The relentlessly pursued thesis is nuanced by the clarification that strict Bayesianism is not an inviolable recipe for automatic decisions but rather a box of tools that can only be used effectively when controlled by human judgment or “art” in modeling (11.7). For example, when Lindley intuitively finds that the prior distribution under his model conflicts with observations, he reframes its prior probabilities as conditional on the truth of the original model by crafting a larger model. Such ingenuity demonstrates that Bayesian probability calculations cannot shackle his actual beliefs. (This suggests that mechanically following the Dutch book argument to the point of absurdity might not discredit strict Bayesianism as decisively as thought.) Similarly, Frank Lad, called “the purest of the pure” [G. Shafer, J. Am. Stat. Assoc. 94 (1999), no. 446, 645–656 (pp. 648–649), doi:10.1080/01621459.1999.10474158] and the best-informed [D. V. Lindley, J. Royal Stat. Soc. Ser. D 49 (2000), no. 3, 293–337] of the advocates of this school, permits replacing a poorly predicting model with one that reflects “a new understanding”, an enlightenment that no algorithm can impart [F. Lad, Operational subjective statistical methods, Wiley Ser. Probab. Statist. Appl. Probab. Statist., Wiley, New York, 1996 (6.6.4); MR1421323 (98m:62009)]. Leonard Savage, a leading critic of non-Bayesian statistical methods, likewise admitted that he was “unable to formulate criteria for selecting these small worlds [in which strict Bayesianism applies] and indeed believe[d] that their selection may be a matter of judgment and experience about which it is impossible to enunciate complete and sharply defined general principles” [L. J. Savage, The foundations of statistics, Wiley, New York, 1954 (2.5); MR0063582 (16,147a)]. The Bayesian lumberjacks have evidently learned when to stop chopping and sharpen the axe. This recalls the importance of the skill of the scientist as handed down and developed within the guild of scientists and never quite articulated, let alone formalized [M. Polanyi, Personal knowledge: towards a post-critical philosophy, Univ. Chicago Press, Chicago, IL, 1962]. The explicit acknowledgement of the role of this tacit knowledge in science may serve as a warning against relying on statistical models as if they were not only useful but also right [see M. van der Laan, Amstat News 2015, no. 452, 29–30].
While the overall argument for strict Bayesianism will command the assent of many readers, some will wonder whether there are equally compelling counter-arguments that would explain why so few statisticians work under that viewpoint. That doubt will be largely offset by the considerable authority Lindley has earned as one of the preeminent developers of the statistics discipline as it is known today. His many enduring contributions to the field include two that shed light on the chasm between Bayesian and frequentist probabilities: (1) the presentation of what is known as “Lindley’s paradox” [D. V. Lindley, Biometrika 44 (1957), no. 1-2, 187–192, doi:10.1093/biomet/44.1-2.187] and (2) specifying the conditions a scalar-parameter fiducial or confidence distribution must satisfy to be a Bayesian posterior distribution [D. V. Lindley, J. Royal Stat. Soc. Ser. B 20 (1958), 102–107; MR0095550 (20 #2052)].
Treading into unresolved controversies well outside his discipline, Lindley shares his simple philosophy of science and offers his opinions on how to apply Bayesianism to law, politics, and religion. He invites his readers to share his hope that if people communicate their beliefs and interests in strict Bayesian terms, they would quarrel less (1.7; 10.7), especially if they adopt his additional advice to consider their own religious beliefs to be uncertain (1.4). Lindley even holds forth the teaching that Jesus is the Son of God as having a probability equal to each reader’s degree of belief in its truth but stops short of assessing the utilities needed to place Pascal’s Wager (1.2).
Graduate students in statistics will benefit from Lindley’s introductions to his paradox, explained in Section 14.4 to discredit frequentist hypothesis testing, and the conglomerable rule in Section 12.9. These friendly and concise introductions could effectively supplement a textbook such as [J. B. Kadane, Principles of uncertainty, Texts Statist. Sci. Ser., CRC Press, Boca Raton, FL, 2011; MR2799022 (2012g:62001)], a much more detailed appeal for strict Bayesianism.
On the other hand, simpler works such as [J. S. Hammond, R. L. Keeney and H. Raiffa, Smart choices: a practical guide to making better decisions, Harvard Bus. School Press, Boston, MA, 1999] may better serve as stand-alone guides to mundane decision making. Bridging the logical gap between decision making rules of thumb and mathematical statistics, Understanding uncertainty excels as a straightforward and sensible defense of the strict Bayesian viewpoint. Appreciating Lindley’s stance in all its theoretical simplicity and pragmatic pliability is essential for grasping both the recent history of statistics and the more complex versions of Bayesianism now used by statisticians, scientists, philosophers, and economists.
{For the original edition see [D. V. Lindley, Understanding uncertainty, Wiley, Hoboken, NJ, 2006].}
Reviewed by David R. Bickel
Fiducial nonparametrics
Sonderegger, Derek L.; Hannig, Jan
Fiducial theory for free-knot splines. Contemporary developments in statistical theory, 155–189,
Springer Proc. Math. Stat., 68, Springer, Cham, 2014.
62F12 (62F10 62F99 65D07)
The research reported reflects the recent surge in developments of Fisher’s fiducial argument [S. Nadarajah, S. Bityukov and N. Krasnikov, Stat. Methodol. 22 (2015), 23–46; MR3261595]. The work of this chapter is carried out within the framework of generalized fiducial inference [J. Hannig, Statist. Sinica 19 (2009), no. 2, 491–544; MR2514173 (2010h:62071)], which is built on the functional-model formulation of fiducial statistics [A. P. Dawid, M. Stone and M. Stone, Ann. Statist. 10 (1982), no. 4, 1054–1074; MR0673643 (83m:62008)] rather than on the broadly equivalent confidence-based tradition beginning with [G. N. Wilkinson, J. Roy. Statist. Soc. Ser. B 39 (1977), no. 2, 119–171; MR0652326 (58 #31491)] and generalized by [E. E. M. van Berkum, H. N. Linssen and D. Overdijk, J. Statist. Plann. Inference 49 (1996), no. 3, 305–317; MR1381161 (97k:62007)].
{For the entire collection see MR3149911.}
Reviewed by David R. Bickel
This review first appeared at “Fiducial theory for free-knot splines” (Mathematical Reviews) and is used with permission from the American Mathematical Society.
The likelihood principle as a relation
Evans, Michael
What does the proof of Birnbaum’s theorem prove? (English summary)
Electron. J. Stat. 7 (2013), 2645–2655.
62A01 (62F99)
The author formalizes the theorem in terms of set theory to say that the likelihood relation is the equivalence relation generated by the union of the sufficiency relation and the conditionality relation. He finds the result trivial because it relies on extending the conditionality relation, itself intuitively appealing, to the equivalence relation it generates, which conflicts with usual frequentist reasoning and which may even be meaningless for statistical practice. This viewpoint is supported with a counterexample.
While some would regard the irrelevance of the theorem as repelling an attack on frequentist inference, emboldening the advancement of novel methods rooted in fiducial probability [R. Martin and C. Liu, Statist. Sci. 29 (2014), no. 2, 247–251; MR3264537; cf. J. Hannig, Statist. Sci. 29 (2014), no. 2, 254–258; MR3264539; S. Nadarajah, S. Bityukov and N. Krasnikov, Stat. Methodol. 22 (2015), 23–46; MR3261595], the author criticizes the conditionality principle as formalized by the conditionality relation. The problem he sees is that the equivalence relation generated by the conditionality relation and needed for the applicability of the theorem “is essentially equivalent to saying that it doesn’t matter which maximal ancillary we condition on and it is unlikely that this is acceptable to most frequentist statisticians”.
The author concludes by challenging frequentists to resolve the problems arising from the plurality of maximal ancillary statistics in light of the “intuitive appeal” of the conditionality relation. From the perspective of O. E. Barndorff-Nielsen [Scand. J. Statist. 22(1995), no. 4, 513–522; MR1363227 (96k:62010)], that might be accomplished by developing methods for summarizing and weighing “diverse pieces of evidence”, with some of that diversity stemming from the lack of a unique maximal ancillary statistic for conditional inference.
Reviewed by David R. Bickel
References
- Barndorff-Nielsen, O. E. (1995) Diversity of evidence and Birnbaum’s theorem (with discussion). Scand. J. Statist., 22(4), 513–522. MR1363227 MR1363227 (96k:62010)
- Birnbaum, A. (1962) On the foundations of statistical inference (with discussion). J. Amer. Stat. Assoc., 57, 269–332. MR0138176 MR0138176 (25 #1623)
- Cox, D. R. and Hinkley, D. V. (1974) Theoretical Statistics. Chapman and Hall. MR0370837 MR0370837 (51 #7060)
- Durbin, J. (1970) On Birnbaum’s theorem on the relation between sufficiency, conditionality and likelihood. J. Amer. Stat. Assoc., 654, 395–398.
- Evans, M., Fraser, D. A. S. and Monette, G. (1986) On principles and arguments to likelihood (with discussion). Canad. J. of Statistics, 14, 3, 181–199. MR0859631 MR0859631 (87m:62017)
- Gandenberger, G. (2012) A new proof of the likelihood principle. To appear in the British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.
- Halmos, P. (1960) Naive Set Theory. Van Nostrand Reinhold Co. MR0114756 MR0114756 (22 #5575)
- Helland, I. S. (1995) Simple counterexamples against the conditionality principle. Amer. Statist., 49, 4, 351–356. MR1368487 MR1368487 (96h:62003)
- Holm, S. (1985) Implication and equivalence among statistical inference rules. In Contributions to Probability and Statistics in Honour of Gunnar Blom. Univ. Lund, Lund, 143–155. MR0795054 MR0795054 (86k:62002)
- Jang, G. H. (2011) The conditionality principle implies the sufficiency principle. Working paper.
- Kalbfleisch, J. D. (1975) Sufficiency and conditionality. Biometrika, 62, 251–259. MR0386075 MR0386075 (52 #6934)
- Mayo, D. (2010) An error in the argument from conditionality and sufficiency to the likelihood principle. In Error and Inference: Recent Exchanges on Experimental Reasoning, Reliability and the Objectivity and Rationality of Science (D. Mayo and A. Spanos eds.). Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 305–314. MR2640508 MR2640508
- Robins, J. and Wasserman, L. (2000) Conditioning, likelihood, and coherence: A review of some foundational concepts. J. Amer. Stat. Assoc., 95, 452, 1340–1346. MR1825290 MR1825290
This review first appeared at “What does the proof of Birnbaum’s theorem prove?” (Mathematical Reviews) and is used with permission from the American Mathematical Society.
You must be logged in to post a comment.